Artigo Revisado por pares

The Madhyamaka Concept of Svabhāva : Ontological and Cognitive Aspects

2007; Routledge; Volume: 17; Issue: 1 Linguagem: Inglês

10.1080/09552360701201122

ISSN

1469-2961

Autores

Jan Westerhoff,

Tópico(s)

Classical Philosophy and Thought

Resumo

Abstract This paper considers the philosophical interpretation of the concept of svabhāva, sometimes translated as 'inherent existence' or 'own-being', in the Madyamaka school of Buddhist philosophy. It is argued that svabhāva must be understood as having two different conceptual dimensions, an ontological and a cognitive one. The ontological dimension of svabhāva shows it to play a particular part in theories investigating the most fundamental constituents of the world. Three different understandings of svabhāva are discussed under this heading: svabhāva understood as essence, as substance, and as the true nature of phenomena (absolute svabhāva). The cognitive dimension shows svabhāva as playing an important rôle in our everyday conceptualization of phenomena. Svabhāva is here seen as a superimposition (samāropa) which the mind projects onto the world. Notes Notes [1] See Robinson (1972 Robinson, R. 1972. Did Nagarjuna really refute all philosophical views?. Philosophy East and West, 22: 325–331. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], 326). [2] Garfield (1995 Garfield, J. 1995. The fundamental wisdom of the Middle Way. Translation and commentary of Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar], p. 89), Komito (1987 Komito, DR. 1987. Nāgārjuna's seventy stanzas: a Buddhist psychology of emptiness, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], p. 69). [3] Napper (1989 Napper, E. 1989. Dependent-arising and emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], p. 65). [4] Lopez (1987 Lopez, D. 1987. A study of Svātantrika, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], pp. 445–446). [5] Ruegg (1981 Ruegg, DS. 1981. The literature of the Madhyamika school of philosophy in India, Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz. [Google Scholar], p. 9). [6] This distinction is still alive in contemporary dGe lugs commentarial textbook literature. See the annotated translation of dKon mchogs 'jigs med dbang po's Grup pa'i mtha'i rnam par bzhag pa rin po che'i phreng ba given in Sopa & Hopkins (1976 Sopa, GL and Hopkins, J. 1976. Practice and theory of Tibetan Buddhism, New York: Grove. [Google Scholar], p. 122). [7] Sopa & Hopkins (1976 Sopa, GL and Hopkins, J. 1976. Practice and theory of Tibetan Buddhism, New York: Grove. [Google Scholar], p. 122) refer to these as phenomena's 'conventionally existent nature', their 'true or independent existence', and their 'real and final nature'. Further attempts at differentiating the different usages of svabhāva in Candrakīrti can be found in Schayer (1931 Schayer, S. 1931. Ausgewählte Kapitel aus der Prasannapadā, Krakow: Nakladem Polskiej Akademji Umietjetności. [Google Scholar], xix, p. 55, note 41), who distinguishes four different senses, as well as in de Jong (1972 de Jong, JW. 1972. The problem of the absolute in the Madhyamika school. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 2: 1–6. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 3) and May (1959 May, J. 1959. Prasannapadā Madhyamakavrtti: Douze chapitres traduits du sanscrit et du tibétain, Paris: Adrien-Maisonneuve. [Google Scholar], p. 124, note 328), who distinguish two. Although there are obvious connections with the senses distinguished here the relations between the different senses discussed by the three authors and, in Schayer's case, the distinctness of the four senses given by him are too unclear to make an attempt at comparison worthwhile. [8] maraṇan ti kho mahārāja etaṃ adiṭṭhasaccānaṃ tāsaniyaṃ ṭhānaṃ … maraṇass' eso mahārāja sarasabhāvatejo tassa sarasabhāvatejena sakilesā sattā maranassa tasanti bhāyanti (Trenckner, 1928 Trenckner, V. 1928. The Milindapañho, London: Royal Asiatic Society. [Google Scholar], p. 149). For a translation see Davids (1890, p. 211). [9] svabhāva evaiṣạṃ svalakṣaṇam | sāmāyalakṣaṇam tu anityatā saṃskṛtānām. Bhāṣya on Vasubandhu (1970–1973 Vasubandhu. 1970–1973. Abhidharmakośa and Bhāṣya of Ācārya Vasubandhu with the Sphutārthā commentary of Ācārya Yaśomitra, Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati. [Google Scholar], 6:14). For further references see Williams (1981 Williams, P. 1981. On the Abhidharma ontology. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 9: 227–257. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], p. 243). [10] svabhāvena parabhāvaviyogataḥ (Vasubandhu, 1970–1973 Vasubandhu. 1970–1973. Abhidharmakośa and Bhāṣya of Ācārya Vasubandhu with the Sphutārthā commentary of Ācārya Yaśomitra, Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati. [Google Scholar], 1:18). [11] According to the Buddhist interpretation these characteristics are being impermanent, unsatisfactory, and devoid of self (Ronkin, 2005 Ronkin, N. 2005. Early Buddist metaphysics: The making of a philosophical Tradition, London: Routledge. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], pp. 114–115). [12] Note that this sense of svabhāva is not to be equated with that of haecceity or quiddity. An haecceity or 'individual essence' is a property only a single individual can have (the socratesness of Socrates is a stock example). But svabhāva in the sense discussed here is shareable. The svabhāva of fire is heat, a characteristic which cannot just be instantiated by fire, but also for example by water (even though heat does not constitute the svabhāva of water). [13] agnerauṣṇyam hi loke tadavyabhicāritvātsvabhāva ityucyate tadevauṣṇyamapsūpalabhyamānaṃ parapratyayasaṃbūtatvātkṛtrimatvānna svabhāva iti (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 241, lines 8–9). A similar characterization of solidity (khara) as the invariable specific quality and thus svabhāva of earth is given in the Madhyāntavibhāgaṭīkā (Williams, 1981 Williams, P. 1981. On the Abhidharma ontology. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 9: 227–257. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], pp. 242–243). [14] Ames (1982 Ames, W. 1982. The notion of svabhāva in the thought of Candrakīrti. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 10: 161–177. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], 170). [15] Buddhapālita, however, clearly has the notion of essence-svabhāva in mind when claims that the aim of Nāgārjuna was to teach the svabhāva (ngo bo nyid) of dependent origination (P 180a:3–4; Walleser, 1913–1914 Walleser, M. 1913–1914. Buddhapālita's Mūlamadhyamakavṛtti, vol. 16, St Petersburg: Bibliotheca Buddhica. [Google Scholar], 4:16–17). As dependent origination identified with emptiness is the exact opposite of svabhāva this expression would constitute a contradictio in adiecto unless we realize that Buddapālita wants to say that Nāgārjuna teaches the specific quality of dependent origination. [16] Iyengar (1927 Iyengar, HHR. 1927. The Ekaślokaśastra of Nāgārjuna Bodhisattva. Journal of Mysore University, 1: 158–162. [Google Scholar], p. 160). Another translation of this passage of the śastra can be found in Edkins (1893 Edkins, J. 1893. Chinese Buddhism. A volume of sketches, historical, descriptive, and critical, London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner. [Google Scholar], pp. 307–307). We might want to note, however, that Lindtner (1982 Lindtner, C. 1982. Nagarjuniana. Studies in the writings and philosophy of Nāgārjuna, Copenhagen: Akademisk Forlag. [Google Scholar], p. 16) classifies this text as 'most probably not genuine'. [17] Some information on the conceptual relationship between svabhāva and svalakṣaṇa can be found in Ronkin (2005 Ronkin, N. 2005. Early Buddist metaphysics: The making of a philosophical Tradition, London: Routledge. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 110). [18] Nāgārjuna might here have the Vaiśeṣika conception of the five elements (bhūta) in mind, all of which are substances (dravya) and are taken to have peculiar qualities which distinguish them from the other elements. See Sharma (1960 Sharma, C. 1960. A critical survey of Indian philosophy, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 177). [19] Williams (1981 Williams, P. 1981. On the Abhidharma ontology. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 9: 227–257. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], pp. 236–237). [20] Ronkin (2005 Ronkin, N. 2005. Early Buddist metaphysics: The making of a philosophical Tradition, London: Routledge. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], ch. 3) argues that there was a gradual move away from a basically epistemological understanding of svabhāva as a characteristic mark to individuate different aspects of experience to an ontological understanding, where svabhāva subsumes objects with a particular ontological status. [21] In the contemporary commentarial literature we find occasional reference to the notion of an intrinsic property to spell out the notion of svabhāva (Tillemans, 2001 Tillemans, T. 2001. "Trying to be fair to Madhyamika Buddhism.". In The Numata Yehan Lecture in Buddhism, Canada: University of Calgary. [Google Scholar], p. 14, note 24; Siderits, 2004 Siderits, M. 2004. Causation and emptiness in early Madhyamika. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 32: 393–419. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], p. 117). Intrinsic properties are those which 'things have in virtue of the way they themselves are', while extrinsic properties are had 'in virtue of their relations or lack of relations to other things' (Lewis, 1986 Lewis, DK. 1986. On the plurality of worlds, Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar], p. 61). While it is clear that all properties constitutive of a primary existent must be intrinsic not all intrinsic properties characterize a primary existent. For example the property of being the tallest man in the room is extrinsic (since a man can only have it in relation to the other men in the room), while that of being a man is intrinsic. However, a man is not a primary existent because he is causally, mereologically, and conceptually dependent on a variety of factors. [22] Hayes (1994 Hayes, RP. 1994. Nāgārjuna's appeal. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 22: 299–378. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 311) distinguishes two senses of svabhāva, svabhāva in the sense of identity and svabhāva in the sense of independence. The former expresses it's understanding as svalakṣaṇa, the latter as dravya. Hayes then goes on to argue that Nāgārjuna equivocates between these different readings, thereby rendering his arguments invalid (p. 316). For some comments on this see Taber (1998 Taber, JA. 1998. On Nāgārjuna's so-called fallacies: a comparative approach. Indo-Iranian Journal, 41: 213–244. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar]), Tillemans (2001 Tillemans, T. 2001. "Trying to be fair to Madhyamika Buddhism.". In The Numata Yehan Lecture in Buddhism, Canada: University of Calgary. [Google Scholar]), Siderits (2004 Siderits, M. 2004. Causation and emptiness in early Madhyamika. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 32: 393–419. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], p. 135, note i). [23] na saṃbhavaḥ svabhāvasya yuktaḥ pratyayahetubhiḥ | hetupratyaya saṃbhūtaḥ svabhāvo kṛtako bhavet || svabhāvaḥ kṛtako nāma bhaviṣyati punaḥ kathaṃ | akṛtrimaḥ svabhāvo hi nirapekṣaḥ paratra ca (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], pp. 259–262). [24] tasya cedaṃ lakśaṇaṃ akṛtrimaḥ svabhāva hi nirapekśaḥ paratra ca (La Vallée Pousin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 265, lines 5–6). See also Candrakīrti's commentary on Āryadeva's Catuḥsátaka 12:13 de la bdag ces bya ba ni gang zhig dngos po rnams kyi gzhan la rag ma las pa'i ngo bo rang bzhin te med pa ni bdgag med pa'o 'Here "self" is a self-existent object which does not depend on other objects. The non-existence [of such an object] is selflessness.' P5266, 98, 265.17. See also Tillemans (1990 Tillemans, TJF. 1990. Materials for the study of Āryadeva, Dharmapāla and Candrakīrti, Wien: Universität Wien. [Google Scholar], p. 126). [25] See Tillemans (2001 Tillemans, T. 2001. "Trying to be fair to Madhyamika Buddhism.". In The Numata Yehan Lecture in Buddhism, Canada: University of Calgary. [Google Scholar], pp. 5–6). [26] … avicārataśca laukikapadārthānāmastitvāt | yathaiva hi rūpādivyatirekeṇa vicāyamāṇa ātmā na saṃbhavati (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 67:7–8; Ruegg, 2002 Ruegg, DS. 2002. Two prolegomena to Madhyamaka philosophy, Vienna: Arbeitskreis für Tibetische und Buddhistische Studien. [Google Scholar], p. 117). [27] Trenckner (1928 Trenckner, V. 1928. The Milindapañho, London: Royal Asiatic Society. [Google Scholar], p. 27), Davids (1890, p. 44). [28] Principes, I, 51. [29] Keyt (1963 Keyt, D. 1963. Wittgenstein's notion of an object. Philosophical Quarterly, 13: 13–25. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar]); Proops (2004 Proops, I. 2004. Wittgenstein on the substance of the world. European Journal of Philosophy, 12: 106–126. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar]). [30] A detailed discussion of different kinds of dependence relations can be found in Simons (1987 Simons, P. 1987. Parts. A study in ontology, Oxford: Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar], ch. 8). Our notion of existential dependence is called 'generic dependence' by Simons. [31] In his (1964, 154:6–155:1) (which constitutes a commentary on the Grub mtha' chen mo of 'Jams dbyangs bzhad pa (1648–1721)) Ngag dbang dpal ldan (1797–?) refers to these three kinds of dependence as 'phrad ba (prāpya), ltos ba (apekṣya) and brten pa (pratītya), respectively. See Magee (1999 Magee, W. 1999. The nature of things. Emptiness and essence in the Geluk world, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], pp. 56–57); Hopkins (1983 Hopkins, J. 1983. Meditation on emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], pp. 166–177); Komito (1987 Komito, DR. 1987. Nāgārjuna's seventy stanzas: a Buddhist psychology of emptiness, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], p. 1190), Gyatso (2005 Gyasto, L. 2005. The harmony of emptiness and dependent-arising , (2nd rev. ed.), Dharamsala: Library of Tibetan Works and Archives. [Google Scholar], pp. 20–21). [32] Ngag dbang dpal ldan (1964 Ngag dbang dpal ldan. 1964. Grub mtha' chen mo'i mchan 'grel dka' gnad mdud grol blo gsal gces nor, Sarnath: Pleasure of Elegant Sayings Printing Press. [Google Scholar], 154:6–155:1); Gyatso (2005 Gyasto, L. 2005. The harmony of emptiness and dependent-arising , (2nd rev. ed.), Dharamsala: Library of Tibetan Works and Archives. [Google Scholar], 33, 43–44, 59–62). [33] pha bu ma yin bu pha min de nyis phan tshun med min la de nyis cig car yang min ltar yan lag bcu gnyis de bzhin no (Tola & Dragonetti, 1987 Tola, F and Dragonetti, C. 1987. Śūnyatāsaptati. The seventy Kārikās on voidness (according to the Svavṛtti) of Nāgārjuna. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 15: 1–55. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], pp. 13, 26). [34] The father–son example is also used in verses 49–50 of the Vigrahavyāvartanī. See also 8:12 and 10:10 of the Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. [35] Oetke (1989 Oetke, C. 1989. Rationalismus und Mystik in der Philosophie Nāgārjunas.. Studien zur Indologie und Iranistik, 15: 1–39. [Google Scholar], p. 11) claims that 'the assumption of isomorphism or identity of logical and causal dependence relations [which correspond to our notional and existential dependence relations] explains a significant part of Nāgārjuna's arguments and simultaneously elucidates numerous apparent difficulties'. [36] The failure to distinguish between existential and notional dependence has resulted in considerable confusion in the contemporary commentarial literature, primarily in connection with the so-called principle of coexisting counterparts (Taber, 1998 Taber, JA. 1998. On Nāgārjuna's so-called fallacies: a comparative approach. Indo-Iranian Journal, 41: 213–244. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 216) Ruegg (1977 Ruegg, DS. 1977. The use of the four positions of the catuṣkoṭi and the problem of the description of reality in Māhāyana Buddhism. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 5(5): 1–171. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar]) calls it 'the principle of the complementarity of binary concepts and terms'] which is supposed to say that 'a thing cannot be a certain type unless its counterpart exists simultaneously with it'. Far from being 'a blatant contradiction of common sense' (Taber, 1998 Taber, JA. 1998. On Nāgārjuna's so-called fallacies: a comparative approach. Indo-Iranian Journal, 41: 213–244. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 238) it expresses an obvious truth about notional dependencies: something cannot be Northern England unless Southern England exists at the same time. It is only if we think that notional dependence is the very same thing as existential dependence that we can accuse Nāgārjuna of being unable to distinguish 'between saying that a thing exists at all and saying that it exists under a given description' (Hayes, 1994 Hayes, RP. 1994. Nāgārjuna's appeal. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 22: 299–378. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 315). For more (unfortunately not very clear) discussion of this matter see Taber (1998 Taber, JA. 1998. On Nāgārjuna's so-called fallacies: a comparative approach. Indo-Iranian Journal, 41: 213–244. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar]). [37] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 264, line 1). [38] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 260). [39] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 260). [40] Schayer (1931 Schayer, S. 1931. Ausgewählte Kapitel aus der Prasannapadā, Krakow: Nakladem Polskiej Akademji Umietjetności. [Google Scholar], p. xix) argues that the Mādhyamika denies the existence of essence-svabhāva. As everything is causally produced 'there is no property which could never be missing from a particular object' (p. 55, note 41). The important point to get is that saying some property is part of the essence-svabhāva of an object of type X does not mean it could never the missing from X, but that if it was missing we would not consider it to be of type X. [41] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 260). [42] Ames (1982 Ames, W. 1982. The notion of svabhāva in the thought of Candrakīrti. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 10: 161–177. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 170). [43] Siderits (2004 Siderits, M. 2004. Causation and emptiness in early Madhyamika. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 32: 393–419. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar], pp. 118–119). [44] Most classifications distinguish either four or five kinds of arguments; there are also slight variations concerning which arguments are subsumed under which heading. For details see Tillemans (1984 Tillemans, T. 1984. Two Tibetan texts on the 'neither one nor many' argument for śūnyatā. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 12: 357–388. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], pp. 371–372, note 16). [45] vajrakaṇa, rdo rje gzegs. [46] sadāsatutpadapratiṣedha, yod med skye 'gog. [47] catuṣkoṭyutpādapratiṣedha, mu bzhi skye 'gog. [48] pratītyasamutpādahetu, rten cing 'brel ba'I gtan tshigs. [49] ekānekaviyogahetu, gcig du bral gyi gtan tshigs. [50] Hopkins (1983 Hopkins, J. 1983. Meditation on emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], pp. 132–150, 639–650). [51] Tillemans (1984 Tillemans, T. 1984. Two Tibetan texts on the 'neither one nor many' argument for śūnyatā. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 12: 357–388. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 361). The temporal reading of this argument is not always so clear. Sometimes (Tillemans 1984 Tillemans, T. 1984. Two Tibetan texts on the 'neither one nor many' argument for śūnyatā. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 12: 357–388. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 361) it is argued that the diamond slivers and the refutation of the production from the existent or non-existent are to be distinguished by the fact that the first analyses the cause, the second the effect. This analysis then investigates whether a cause produces and existent, a non-existent, a both existent and non-existent or a neither existent nor non-existent effect. See Hopkins (1983 Hopkins, J. 1983. Meditation on emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], pp. 151–154). [52] Some discussion is in Hopkins (1983 Hopkins, J. 1983. Meditation on emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], pp. 155–160). [53] Hopkins (1983 Hopkins, J. 1983. Meditation on emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], pp. 161–173). [54] See Hopkins (1983 Hopkins, J. 1983. Meditation on emptiness, London: Wisdom. [Google Scholar], pp. 176–196). [55] La Vallée Poussin (1988–1990 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1988–1990. Abhidharmakośabhāṣyam, Berkeley, CA: Asian Humanities Press. (L. M. Pruden, Trans.) [Google Scholar], pp. 68–70); Dhammajoti (2004 Dhammajoti, KL. 2004. Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, Sri Lanka: Centre for Buddhist Studies. [Google Scholar], pp. 147–148). [56] La Vallée Poussin (1988–1990 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1988–1990. Abhidharmakośabhāṣyam, Berkeley, CA: Asian Humanities Press. (L. M. Pruden, Trans.) [Google Scholar], p. 88). [57] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, 5:7. [58] See Siderits (2003 Siderits, M. 2003. Personal identity and Buddhist philosophy, Aldershot: Ashgate. [Google Scholar], pp. 120–123). [59] The ontological status of space is a controversial issue in the Buddhist literature. While not being one of the four mahābhūtas (Dhammajoti, 2004 Dhammajoti, KL. 2004. Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, Sri Lanka: Centre for Buddhist Studies. [Google Scholar], pp. 148–149) the Abhidharmakośabhāṣya nevertheless includes it together with these in a list of six elements or dhātus (La Vallée Poussin, 1988–1990 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1988–1990. Abhidharmakośabhāṣyam, Berkeley, CA: Asian Humanities Press. (L. M. Pruden, Trans.) [Google Scholar], p. 88). Moreover, the *Abhidharmamahāhavibhāṣaśāstra argues that space can be a dominant condition (adhipatipratyaya) for the mahābhūtas and therefore possesses svabhāva (Dhammajoti, 2004 Dhammajoti, KL. 2004. Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, Sri Lanka: Centre for Buddhist Studies. [Google Scholar], p. 384). Problems with properties of the mahābhūtas will therefore equally apply to space. [60] nākāśaṃ vidyate kiṃ citpūrvam ākāśalakṣaṇat alakṣaṇaṃ prasjyeta syātpūrvaṃ yadi lakṣaṇāt Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 5:1 (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 129:6–7). [61] alakṣaṇo na kaścicca bhāvaḥ saṃvidyate kva cit, Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 5:2a (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 129:15). [62] Armstrong (1997 Armstrong, DM. 1997. A world of states of affairs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], pp. 109–110, 123–126). [63] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 130), Siderits (2003 Siderits, M. 2003. Personal identity and Buddhist philosophy, Aldershot: Ashgate. [Google Scholar], p. 121). [64] nālakṣaṇe lakṣaṇasya pravṛttirna salakṣaṇe | salakṣaṇālakṣaṇābhyāṃ nāpyanyatra pravartate Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 5:3 (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 130:7–8). [65] See Williams (1953 Williams, DC. 1953. The elements of being.. Review of Metaphysics, 7(3–18): 171–192. [Google Scholar]) for an early example, Bacon (1995 Bacon, J. 1995. Universals and property instances. The alphabet of being, Oxford: Blackwell. [Google Scholar]) for a more recent discussion. [66] lakṣyasyānupapattau ca lakṣaṇasyāpy asaṃbhavaḥ, Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 5:4b (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 131:10). [67] Siderits (2003 Siderits, M. 2003. Personal identity and Buddhist philosophy, Aldershot: Ashgate. [Google Scholar], pp. 122–123). [68] A discussion of different ways of individuating tropes is in Schaffer (2001 Schaffer, J. 2001. The individuation of tropes. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79(2): 247–257. [Taylor & Francis Online], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar]). [69] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 5:3,5. [70] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 5:4–5. [71] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 24:38 ajātam aniruddhaṃ ca kūṭasthaṃ ca bhaviṣyati | vicitrābhir avasthābhiḥ svabhāve rahitaṃ jagat (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 513:10–11). Other passages dealing with the permanence of svabhāva include 13:4, 21:17, 23:24, and 24: 22–26. [72] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 13:3a, 4b–5 bhāvānāṃ niḥsvabhāvatvamanyathābhāvadarśanāt | … kasya syādanyathābhāvaḥ svabhāvo yadi vidyate || tasyaiva nānyathābhāvo nāpyanyasyaiva yujyate | yuvā na jīryate yasmādyosmājjīrṇo na jīryate (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 240:8–241:16). [73] See Siderits (2003 Siderits, M. 2003. Personal identity and Buddhist philosophy, Aldershot: Ashgate. [Google Scholar], pp. 124–125) for a description of this view. [74] See von Rospat (1995 von Rospat, A. 1995. The Buddhist doctrine of momentariness, Stuttgart: Franz Steiner. [Google Scholar]). [75] Siderits (2003 Siderits, M. 2003. Personal identity and Buddhist philosophy, Aldershot: Ashgate. [Google Scholar], p. 125). [76] sangs rgyas rnams kyi don dam pa ni rang bzhin nyid yin zhing | de yang bslu ba med pa nyid kyis don dam pa'i bden pa yin la | de ni de rnams kyi so sor rang gis rig par bya ba yin no (La Vallée Poussin, 1912 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1912. Madhyamakāvatāra of Candrakīrti, St. Pétersbourg: Académie Impériale des Sciences. [Google Scholar], p. 108, line 16–19). [77] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 261). [78] La Vallée Poussin (1912 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1912. Madhyamakāvatāra of Candrakīrti, St. Pétersbourg: Académie Impériale des Sciences. [Google Scholar], p. 107, line 15). See also p. 306. [79] Some of the synonyms for absolute svabhāva Candrakīrti gives include 'objecthood of objects' (dharmānām dharmatā), 'intrinsic nature' (tatsvarūpam), 'original nature' (prakṛti), 'emptiness' (śūnyatā), 'lack of svabhāva' (naiḥsvābhāvyam), 'thusness' (tathatā), 'complete non-origination' (sarvaśa anutpāda), and 'being thus, changelessness, ever-abidingness' (tathābhāvo 'vikaritvam sadaiva sthāyitā) (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], pp. 264–265). [80] La Vallée Poussin (1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], p. 265). [81] khyad par gsum dang ldan pa (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 643:12), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:194). This characterization follows Nāgārjuna's discussion of svabhāva in Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 15:2 and 8. See also Magee (1999 Magee, W. 1999. The nature of things. Emptiness and essence in the Geluk world, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], pp. 87–88). [82] rgyu dang rkyen gyis ma bskyed pa (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 643:12–13), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:194). [83] gnas skabs gzhan du mi 'gyur ba (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 643:13), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:194). [84] rnam 'jog gzhan la mi ltos pa (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 643:13), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:194). [85] This is the reason why Tsong kha pa does not regard the three characteristics as sufficient for identifying the object of negation (dgag bya). 'Jam dbyangs bshad pa asks in the mChan bu bzhi: 'di stong nyid kyi khyad par yin pas dgag byar ga la rung 'These [three characteristics] being characteristics of emptiness how could they be the object of negation?' (Jam dbyangs bshad pa et al., 1972 Jam dbyangs bshad pa, Ba so chos kyi rgyal mthsan, Ngag dbang rab rtan sDe drug mkan chen, and Bra sti dge shes rin chen don grub. 1972. mNyam med rje btsun tsong kha pa chen pos mdzad pa'i byang chub lam rim chen mo's dka' ba'i gnad rnams mchan bu bzhi'i sgo nas legs bar bshad par bshad pa theg chen lam gyi gsal sgron., New Delhi: Chos 'phel legs ldan. [Google Scholar], 387.6). [86] Ames (1982 Ames, W. 1982. The notion of svabhāva in the thought of Candrakīrti. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 10: 161–177. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar], p. 174). [87] rang gi ngo bos grub pa (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 648:5), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:199). [88] kun brtags (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 644:20), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar] 3:196). [89] don dam pa'i bden pa ni chos nyid la rang bzhin du bzhag pa der grub kyang rang bzhin der 'jog byed bcos ma min pa dang | gzhan la mi ltos pa ni rang gi ngo bos grub pa'i rang bzhin der cung zad kyang med pa (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 648:3–5), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:199). An alternative translation of this passage is in Magee (1999 Magee, W. 1999. The nature of things. Emptiness and essence in the Geluk world, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], pp. 92–93). [90] rang gi ngo bo'i sgo nas yul gyi steng du grub pa. The relevant passage from Ngag dbang dpal ldan is cited in Magee (1999 Magee, W. 1999. The nature of things. Emptiness and essence in the Geluk world, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], pp. 94–95). [91] (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 1985 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 1985. Lam Rim Chen Mo, Qinghai: Tso Ngön (Qinghai) People's Press. [Google Scholar], 644:18–645:1), (Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa, 2000–2004 Tsong kha pa bLo bzang grags pa. 2000–2004. The great treatise on the stages of the path to enlightenment, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], 3:196). [92] See Magee (1999 Magee, W. 1999. The nature of things. Emptiness and essence in the Geluk world, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], p. 96). [93] The problem of the differentiation between substance-svabhāva and absolute svabhāva was later further elaborated in the Tibetan tradition in the context of the debate over self-emptiness (rang stong) and other-emptiness (gzhan stong). For further details see Hookham (1991 Hookham, SK. 1991. The Buddha within. Tathagatagarbha doctrine according to the Shentong interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]), Magee (1999 Magee, W. 1999. The nature of things. Emptiness and essence in the Geluk world, Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion. [Google Scholar], pp. 103–115). [94] I thank Mattia Salvini for helpful discussion of this point. [95] na tadasti na cāpi nāsti svarūpataḥ (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 264:3). Candrakīrti uses the synonymous term svarūpa 'intrinsic nature' instead of svabhāva in this passage. [96] rab rib, timira. [97] La Vallée Poussin (1912 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1912. Madhyamakāvatāra of Candrakīrti, St. Pétersbourg: Académie Impériale des Sciences. [Google Scholar], 6:29; p. 106, line 10–110, line 3). [98] avidyāyāṃ niruddhāyāṃ samskārāṇāmasaṃbhavaḥ | āvidyāyā nirodhastu jñānenāsyaiva bhāvanāt || tasya tasya nirodhena tattannābhipravartate | duḥkhaskandhaḥ kevalo 'yamevaṃ samyagnirudhyate, Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 26: 11–12, (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], pp. 558–559). [99] See Willams and Tribe (2000 Willams, P and Tribe, A. 2000. Buddhist thought, London: Routledge. [Google Scholar], pp. 62–72) for an overview. [100] yo hi protītyasamutpādaṃ samyak paśyatīti sa sūkṣmasyāpi bhāvasya na svarūpamupalabhate (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 559:3–4). [101] Mūlamadhyamakakārikā 16:10. See Tanji (2000 Tanji, T. 2000. "On Samāropa". In Wisdom, Compassion, and the search for understanding, Edited by: Silk, J. 347–368. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. [Google Scholar], 352, 355). [102] This does deny that establishing what is 'really meant' by Nāgārjuna's arguments is in many cases more difficult to establish than for other philosophers (Tillemans, 2001 Tillemans, T. 2001. "Trying to be fair to Madhyamika Buddhism.". In The Numata Yehan Lecture in Buddhism, Canada: University of Calgary. [Google Scholar], p. 17), (Griffiths, 2000 Griffiths, P. 2000. Review of David Burton's Emptiness Appraised. Journal of Buddhist Ethics, 7: 22–25. [Google Scholar], p. 24). Internal coherence of the arguments presented and external coherence with the context of Nāgārjuna's thoughts is all I think to be reasonably expected from a presentation such as this. [103] tasmādanuppanā bhāvā ityevaṃ tāvadviparītasvarūpādhyāropapratipakṣeṇa prathamaprakaraṇārambhaḥ | idānīṃ kvacidyaḥkaścidviśeṣo 'dhyāropitastadviśeṣāpākaraṇārthaṃ śeṣaprakaraṇārabhyaḥ (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], pp. 10–11). [104] saṃsārādhvani vartamānānāmavidyāviparyāsānugamānmṛṣārtha eva skandhasamāropaḥ satyatah pratibhāsamānaḥ padārthalattvadarśanasamīpasthānām na pratibhāsate (La Vallée Poussin, 1903–1913 La Vallée Poussin, Lde. 1903–1913. Mūlamadhyamakakārikās de Nāgārjuna avec la Prasannapadā commentaire de Candrakīrti, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. [Google Scholar], 347:1–3). [105] Tillemans (2001 Tillemans, T. 2001. "Trying to be fair to Madhyamika Buddhism.". In The Numata Yehan Lecture in Buddhism, Canada: University of Calgary. [Google Scholar], p. 18). [106] For the earliest description of the phi phenomenon see Wertheimer (1912 Wertheimer, M. 1912. Experimentelle Studien über das Sehen von Bewegung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 61: 161–265. [Google Scholar]), further results and interpretations are in Dennett (1991 Dennett, D. 1991. Consciousness explained, Boston: Little, Brown. [Google Scholar]) and Hoffman (1998 Hoffman, DD. 1998. Visual intelligence. How we create what we see, New York: W.W. Norton. [Google Scholar]). [107] The problem of 'object permanence', i.e. of the question when two distinct perceptions of an object are regarded as being caused by a single thing has been investigated extensively in developmental psychology. See Piaget (1937 Piaget, J. 1973. La construction du réel chez l'enfant, Paris: Delacheux et Niestlé. [Google Scholar]) and Spelke (1990 Spelke, E. 1990. Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science, 14: 29–56. [Crossref], [Web of Science ®] , [Google Scholar]) for two now classical discussion. An interesting related experiment is described in Subbotskii (1991 Subbotskii, EV. 1991. Existence as a psychological problem: object permanence in adults and preschool children. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 14(1): 67–82. [Crossref] , [Google Scholar]). [108] LaBerge et al. (1986 LaBerge, S, Levitan, L and Dement, WC. 1986. Lucid dreaming: Physiological correlates of consciousness during REM sleep. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 7: 251–258. [Google Scholar]). [109] LaBerge (1991 LaBerge, S. 1991. Exploring the world of lucid dreaming, New York: Ballantine. [Google Scholar]). [110] Further investigation of our perceptions of the self, of causality, or of mereological relations might provide yet other aspects which cohere with the traditional view of svabhāva.

Referência(s)
Altmetric
PlumX