Artigo Acesso aberto Revisado por pares

Time to abandon the term ‘patient concordance’

2007; Wiley; Volume: 64; Issue: 5 Linguagem: Inglês

10.1111/j.1365-2125.2007.02971_2.x

ISSN

1365-2125

Autores

Jeffrey K Aronson,

Tópico(s)

Healthcare Systems and Technology

Resumo

Originally, the definition of concordance ‘impl[ied] that the prescriber and patient should come to an agreement about the regimen that the patient will take’, as I wrote in my recent editorial [1]. I also pointed out that compliance can mean ‘Accord, concord, agreement; amicable relations (between parties)’, which seems to me to be in concord with this definition of concordance. This may partly explain the confusion between these terms, reflected in the titles of some publications, in which ‘concordance’ is used as a synonym for ‘compliance’ or ‘adherence’[2–4]. In fact, the definition of concordance has shifted since it was first invented. The original definition was ‘an agreement reached after negotiation between a patient and a health care professional that respects the beliefs and wishes of the patient in determining whether, when and how medicines are to be taken’[5]. However, as I argue below, a negotiated agreement is not relevant to the interaction between a clinician and a patient, and the focus of concordance has therefore shifted from the consultation to how to communicate with and support the patient [5], which are relevant. Bell et al. also suggest that a consultation between a clinician and a patient is a negotiation [6]. It is not, as those who regularly treat patients know. A 55-year-old man suddenly develops crushing retrosternal chest pain while mowing his lawn. The pain radiates to his neck and jaw and down his left arm. He has tingling in the fingers of his left hand and a feeling of impending doom. An electrocardiogram shows widespread ST segment elevation in the anterior leads, with Q waves and T wave inversion, and his serum troponin concentration is markedly raised. I tell him that he has had a heart attack and explain why I have reached that conclusion and how it has probably happened. There is no negotiation. The diagnosis is definitive – take it or leave it. If he does not accept the diagnosis he can, if he wants, consult another clinician. But whether he agrees or not, he has had a heart attack. Had the diagnosis been less clear, doubts could have been discussed and further investigations suggested, but there would still be no negotiation. He can refuse further investigations if he prefers, but no amount of agreement or disagreement will alter the circumstances. Now I suggest to him that thrombolytic therapy is likely to be beneficial, since there is good evidence that he will benefit from such treatment and that the potential benefit will outweigh the potential harm. Again there is no negotiation. He can refuse the treatment, but he cannot, for example, negotiate for a delay while he goes home to finish some work, or for treatment with only half the recommended dose, or for a tablet instead of an injection. I have a responsibility to tell him about the benefits and harms and the balance between them, couching my explanations in terms that he will understand, and giving him the opportunity to ask questions. His responsibility is to decide whether the treatment is acceptable to him and to tell me in good time (since the longer he waits the less effective the treatment will be). If he accepts the treatment I have the further responsibility to administer it properly, to monitor its effects and to take further necessary actions, explaining each step. In a discussion with him about resuscitation in the event of a cardiac arrest I would follow his wishes; in that case the position is reversed – I would not want to negotiate otherwise. A search of Pubmed for papers whose titles include the word ‘concordance’ yields about 1300 results, well over 95% of which are nothing to do with agreement between clinicians and patients. They use the term in the sense of correspondence. For example ‘physician and patient gender concordance’ means that the physician and patient are of the same sex [7]. Similarly, ‘patient–physician racial and ethnic concordance’ means that they are of the same race or ethnic origin [8]. ‘Language concordance’ is the use and understanding of the same language [9]. In all these and other cases [10–12] the correspondence is perfect. However, clinicians' views about therapy can never be perfectly concordant with those of patients. As Bell et al. put it, ‘How individual patients value the risks and benefits of a particular medicine may differ from the value assigned by their clinicians’[6]; indeed, such a difference generally occurs. The best that can be hoped for is that the clinician explains clearly and advises appropriately and the patient decides whether to accept the advice and to adhere to the proffered therapy, with suitable support from the clinician, or to reject the advice, either outright or by subsequent non-adherence (adherence not always being beneficial). Concordance has become a shibboleth that has been accepted uncritically in certain quarters in the absence of evidence of its benefits and harms and of the balance between them. Authors do not write about testing the concept of concordance. They write about achieving concordance [13], promoting it [14], improving it [15], enhancing it [4], even when they admit at the same time that supportive evidence of benefit is rare [13] and although doubts about its benefits have been expressed and possible harms mentioned [16]. What evidence there is, is limited. Take ‘concordance therapy’, for example. A search of Pubmed for the term yields four references, of which three are interventional studies: in the management of akathisia mental health nurses can, it is suggested, ‘safely prescribe psychiatric medication in combination with concordance therapy’[17] in 19 patients, for whom antidepressants had been prescribed, concordance therapy was said to be ‘acceptable and feasible’ and the authors concluded that it ‘show[ed] sufficient promise of efficacy to justify an adequately powered R[andomized] C[ontrolled] T[rial]’[18] in 10 subjects with bipolar I disorder, of whom eight had concordance therapy, there were small improvements in attitudes towards lithium and in self-reported adherence [19]. There is no evidence on the possible harms of such therapies. Some of the types of research on concordance that are desirable have been mentioned in a thoughtful review [5], and the National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence in the UK is conducting a critical appraisal of the evidence on shared decision making, although the report is not expected until December 2008 [20]. Not all patients want to be more involved in decisions about their management. In a study of 344 patients with rheumatoid arthritis, 78% thought that patients should feel free to make everyday decisions about medical problems, but 75% thought that doctors should make important decisions and >50% thought that patients should go along with doctors' decisions even if they disagreed with them [21]. On the other hand, many patients want more information – in the same study, significantly more patients wanted information than wanted to be involved in making decisions. However, up to 80% of information given to patients during medical consultations is forgotten at once, and almost half of what is remembered is remembered incorrectly [22]; measures to improve this would be welcome. More education of clinicians in the practical aspects of prescribing is also desirable [23]. The word of choice to describe a patient's medicine-taking behaviour is ‘adherence’[5]. The word ‘concordance’, when used to imply a negotiated agreement between prescriber and patient, is misleading and inaccurate. It was invented with excellent intentions [24] but has failed to live up to expectations. We should ditch it and talk instead about what really matters to patients in their conversations with health care professionals – the quality of communication and support that they receive.

Referência(s)