Artigo Revisado por pares

Narrow Content

2021; Duke University Press; Volume: 130; Issue: 3 Linguagem: Inglês

10.1215/00318108-8998929

ISSN

1558-1470

Autores

Ethan Jerzak,

Tópico(s)

Theology and Philosophy of Evil

Resumo

It has seemed to many that what I think is up to me. I go about life representing the world with thoughts, and my intrinsic state fixes the content of those thoughts—fixes, that is, what they require of the world in order to be true. Call this idea internalism about mental content (henceforth, internalism). Juhani Yli-Vakkuri and John Hawthorne (henceforth, YVH) have written a book that attempts to refute internalism in all its reasonable manifestations.There is much of value in Narrow Content. The central argument, with its protagonist Mirror Man, constitutes a formidable stumbling-block that all future internalists will have to contend with. And the authors have done substantial work to iron out a more precise characterization of the conceptual landscape than existed hitherto. That said, the book is not without frustrations, for reasons both stylistic and substantive. Stylistically, while the authors are admirably clear about defining the views at issue, they’re not always great about explaining why the definitions are as they are, especially in cases where their framework is more complicated than what you might have expected. Substantively (and, I’ll argue, relatedly), the authors largely neglect to address one of the most prominent roles certain philosophers (e.g., Daniel Dennett, Robert Stalnaker, and David Lewis) have taken content to play, that of explaining and predicting behavior. It’s not clear, so I’ll argue, that the central argument of the book refutes internalists of that kind.Narrow Content takes up a project invented by Hilary Putnam and Tyler Burge. Putnam (its closest spiritual predecessor) convinced many that the content of our thoughts about water depends on more than us; it depends also on what has caused our water experiences. Here on Earth, that’s H2O, so my thought that I behold water is true just in case I behold H2O. My qualitatively identical twin, on a planet like Earth except that the watery stuff there comprises XYZ, has a thought internally just like mine. But if he beheld H2O, his thought would be false, for his thoughts concern XYZ. Since our qualitatively identical thoughts in our qualitatively identical heads differ in truth, what they require of the world to be true (their content) is not fixed internally.The opponents of Putnam/Burge whom YVH are concerned to refute are those who try nonetheless to find a “theoretically interesting” notion of content shared between me and my twin. Two-dimensionalists, for example, hold that while my twin and I entertain different contents in some sense, we share content in another. On the simplest version, primary contents (the narrow ones) are functions from world-agent pairs ⟨w,a⟩ to truth-values. My twin and I both believe that a beholds the stuff that generally plays the water role for a in w. However, his thought might still be false and mine true, for this content gets evaluated relative to different agents.The central claim of Narrow Content is that enrichments like this will not do. YVH purport to describe a single agent, Mirror Man, who, at a single time, thinks two qualitatively indistinguishable thoughts that differ in truth-value. Think of Mirror Man as Ethan and Twin Ethan crammed into one body. Mirror Man is a left-right symmetric agent. Every time he thinks a thought with his left side, he thinks a corresponding thought with his right. With his right side he perceives Kit Fine, and truly judges him to be human. With his left side he perceives a perfect wax copy of Kit Fine, and falsely judges it to be human. Two qualitatively identical thoughts, same world, same agent, different truth-values. Thus, either more indices are required, or content does not supervene narrowly.This is the core of what YVH call the parameter proliferation argument. Further epicycles abound: whatever new indices the narrow content theorist adds to the supervenience base, YVH whip up some novel variation of the Mirror Man story to supply two thoughts with the same indices of occurrence but intuitively different truth-values.To formalize this argument, YVH must give a definition of internalism that allows them to distinguish simultaneous, qualitatively identical thoughts within a single agent. This constitutes some of the more interesting aspects of the book, and its more frustrating ones. They spend chapter 1—all forty-five pages of it!—defining internalism. Chapter 2 sketches their argument against narrow content. The next two chapters deal with specific job descriptions for content in light of this argument: serving as the referents of that-clauses (chapter 3), and explaining a priori entailment between thoughts (chapter 4). The final two chapters take up the prospects for weakened versions of internalism—weakened by dropping the qualitative supervenience requirement (chapter 5), and by allowing relations between thoughts to figure into the supervenience base (chapter 6).You might be surprised—I was surprised—that it takes forty-five pages to define internalism. Why does it take so long to flesh out the idea that what I think depends only on me? Indeed, Williamson (for example) requires but a paragraph: A centered world α is internally like β if and only if their agents are in exactly the same qualitative physical state. A condition is narrow if and only if it obtains in exactly those centered worlds that are internally alike. Internalism is the view that content-ascribing conditions are narrow.YVH’s definition requires more machinery. The internal part of Williamson’s cases are states of whole agents, and the relevant conditions apply (or not) to whole agents. This won’t do for YVH’s purposes; their definition applies to particular token thoughts within an agent. It relies on what they call the qualitative agential profile (QAP) of a thought, that is, the conjunction of all intrinsic qualitative relations that hold between the thought and its bearer. A content assignment, assigning contents to thoughts, is narrow just in case it supervenes on QAPs. Internalism is the view that there is a theoretically interesting narrow content assignment satisfying plausible conditions.With these definitions in hand, YVH can formulate the Mirror Man argument. Since Mirror Man is symmetric, his left thought l and right thought r have the same QAP. (Assuming, that is, that “being located in the left side of” does not constitute a qualitative relation—more on that later.) So any narrow content assignment must assign l and r the same content, in which case the thoughts, having as they do the same index of evaluation, must be true or false together, contradicting our intuitive judgments of the case.Why, apart from being indispensable for their argument, do YVH think we need to switch from coarse narrowness to QAPs? The answer comes on page 48, in the form of a case purportedly pulling apart narrowness from coarse narrowness. They ask us to imagine two duplicate brains each with a red and a blue hemisphere. Each hemisphere contains exactly one thought. Take a content assignment according to which both brains believe p and q, but in brain 1 the blue hemisphere’s thought gets assigned p whereas in brain 2 the red hemisphere’s does.This, YVH say, is consistent with that content assignment’s being coarsely narrow but not with its being narrow in their sense. The idea is that brain 1 and brain 2 as wholes believe all the same things, and so constitute no counterexample to coarse narrowness. But since which half realizes which belief changes without any corresponding change in the QAP, the content assignment is not narrow.OK, fine, the two notions come apart—but which is closer to the intuitive idea? YVH argue that it must be theirs, on the basis of the following modification: Any possible duplicate of Brain 1 gets p assigned to the blue hemisphere if and only if it located within a mile of a baboon (otherwise the red). “In this example,” YVH contend, “it is clear that the ur-content of a thought depends on the environment of the agent of the thought, so is not intuitively narrow. It is also not narrow according to our definition. Yet content is coarsely narrow in the example” (48). QED; the finer-grained definition that accommodates Mirror Man is actually necessary to elucidate the underlying concept.However, those who accept a minimal kind of holism about propositional attitudes are unlikely to be moved by this argument. YVH bake into the description of the case that brain 1 and brain 2 have thought tokens located in various parts of their brains, and trade on the intuition that if which part realizes which belief depends on whether a baboon is nearby, that content assignment is intuitively wide. But the very idea that distinct thoughts can be pinpointed to specific brain regions is one that many would happily deny. Stalnaker (1990), for instance, denies that we have any way of isolating a particular thought token without reference to content: “It is not at all clear … that one can identify something that is [a] belief or intention in abstraction from its content, something about which we can ask, what would the content of that belief have been if it had been a belief I had on Twin Earth.” Stalnaker’s thought is that we have a grip on the notion of contentful mental states largely by reference to the explanation and prediction of the behavior of agents. To ascribe to Fido the thought that a bone-treat is forthcoming is to expect Fido to behave in certain bone-treat-directed ways—by greedily staring in the direction of the bone-treat closet, for example.YVH are pretty clearly adopting the language-of-thought model that Stalnaker (1984) lambastes. They are happy to assume—indeed as parts of the very descriptions of their critical cases—that thoughts come in tokens, have parts, have physical locations, are intelligible as thoughts independently of their contents (so that different content assignments can assign different contents to the same one), and so on. Officially they are not committed to a specific language of thought thesis, and they acknowledge, for example, that “perhaps some thoughts are diffusely located, perhaps underwritten by the agent’s pattern of behavioural dispositions” (20)—but key moves made later on in the book belie this allowance.This red/blue hemisphere business is precisely one such move. We are to accept as part of the description of the case itself that there is a thought lurking in the red half, and another lurking in the blue half, about which it makes sense to ask about their differing contents. It is hard to imagine Stalnaker acquiescing. The relevant agent may well believe p and q, but that’s as fine-grained as it goes. About no particular entity in his colorfully bifurcated brain does it make any sense to ask, “Is this the thought whose content is p?”Complaints in this vicinity troubled me throughout the book. What makes Mirror Man a single agent, rather than a pair of Siamese twins? What does Mirror Man as a whole believe? (The answer is surprisingly hard to divine from the description offered.) Are his halves functionally integrated? Is it an accident that his halves are symmetric, or is he robustly set up that way? No one can object to YVH providing us with a physical description of an entity and then asking for our intuitions about its beliefs and desires; but to bake into the setup that Mirror Man is a single agent, in which two token thoughts separately occur, each located determinately in a different hemisphere—this is to paper over by fiat some of the most interesting questions about their creature.I suspect that many who incline toward internalism do so partly on the basis of behavioristic inclinations. Every undergraduate has thought: “But Oscar and Twin-Oscar would act in all of the same ways in the presence of their redistributed liquids! Doesn’t that mean something importantly contentful is shared?” Correct or not, that this is a natural way to state the internalistic hunch ought to make one suspicious of the machinery YVH require for their supposed refutation.One final thought. Narrow Content’s central argument relies on the idea that left-right orientation does not constitute a qualitative property. If the property of being located on the left side of its agent were a qualitative property of a thought token, then Mirror Man’s left and right thoughts would differ in QAP. YVH consider a symmetry-breaking response in terms of the different phenomenologies of left and right, but reject it: they must be committed to the idea that “a pair of left and right gloves could be intrinsic duplicates” (90).There are, I am told, chemical molecules called enantiomers that are perfect molecular mirrors of each other. Oranges and lemons, for example, both contain molecules called limonene. It comes in two orientations: one finds limonene+ in oranges and limonene− in lemons. The gustatory difference between the two fruits owes, apparently, to this difference in orientation.Suppose (now counterfactually) that oranges and lemons were perfectly identical, save for the difference in limonene+ vs limonene−. Then if YVH are correct, an orange and a lemon might be perfect qualitative duplicates. Limonene+ and limonene− do not differ in any respect save orientation; their different flavors arise from how they fit into our differently oriented taste buds.However, one looking to bake a lemon tart would consider himself duped, were his grocer to sell him an orange when he requested a lemon. He could quite reasonably complain that he received the wrong kind of thing. Now, perhaps for metaphysical reasons, that complaint is strictly speaking incorrect. Nothing is wrong with the fruit; it’s a perfect qualitative duplicate of one that would yield a proper lemon tart. Something is wrong only with its nonqualitative relation to the baker’s taste buds.If that’s right, then, contrary to what one might have expected, the condition of being a lemon (or a limonene+ molecule) is wide. It depends not only on the intrinsic qualitative properties of the fruit, but also on how its molecules happen to be oriented. But this hardly suggests that its lemonhood is constitutively dependent on its environment in any particularly deep sense. Suppose that left-right orientation is fixed by convention. There is, let us say, a left-handed glove in a Paris vault that fixes what “left” means. Then it’s plausible that lemonhood, while not officially narrow, is wide only in a rather uninteresting sense: the fruit’s intrinsic qualitative properties, together with one further nonqualitative fact relating it to the Paris Glove, plausibly determine its lemonhood.When Oscar was reported to have different beliefs from his twin, this was taken to show that content constitutively depends on the surrounding environment. It’s actual intercourse with actual water that makes my water-thoughts concern H2O. This is what people have in mind when they say that content is wide.Consider now a slight weakening of internalism: A content assignment is quite narrow if and only if it supervenes on a thought’s QAP, together with one further fact: whether it occurs in the same side of its agent as the direction Paris Glove’s thumb points when observing it from the top. Granted this allows some amount of extraqualitative stuff to factor into the supervenience base. But it’s a far cry from the constitutive-environmental-dependence that fans of wide content have advocated. Thought depends on its environment to no greater degree than a lemon’s lemonhood depends on its environment. Bare sameness of orientation with respect to the Paris Glove is all that’s required; other than that, QAP might well suffice. If that is all that the rejection of Narrow Content amounts to, it may not strike many as much.

Referência(s)
Altmetric
PlumX