Artigo Revisado por pares

Alle origini della rappresentazione: La tragedia in Aristotele e Nietzsche

2015; Penn State University Press; Volume: 46; Issue: 2 Linguagem: Inglês

10.5325/jnietstud.46.2.0284

ISSN

1538-4594

Autores

Carlotta Santini,

Tópico(s)

Nietzsche, Schopenhauer, and Hegel

Resumo

Nietzsche's relationship to Aristotle has not been sufficiently emphasized and explored by scholars. Several important studies have been undertaken in the past, but the theme has recently been abandoned in favor of a proliferation of essays on the relationship between Nietzsche and Plato. Yet Nietzsche's relationship with Aristotle is arguably much more profound than that with Plato, since the former served as an essential reference point and a favored source for Nietzsche, especially as regards the Poetics and the Rhetoric. And although scholarly studies have highlighted Nietzsche's criticisms of Aristotle, in fact many more debts than differences can be found in Nietzsche's philosophy. A more profound analysis would show how Nietzsche learned much more from Aristotle than he rejected.In Alle origini della rappresentazione: La tragedia in Aristotele e Nietzsche (At the Origins of Representation: Tragedy in Aristotle and Nietzsche), Antonio Valentini deals with one of the central themes of the Nietzsche-Aristotle relationship, the theory of tragedy. For Valentini, the core of both the Aristotelian and the Nietzschean theory is the concept of representation (in Aristotle's case, the theory of mimesis), which allows tragedy to be considered not only as an artistic genre, but also and especially as an act of cognition. The spectacle represented by tragedy does not limit itself to mere aesthetic entertainment but rather is an “ontologically fundamental” event (9; my translation), since it can tell us something about the world and about our substantial and cognitive relationship with it.The book is divided into two distinct parts, with the second much longer than the first. The first part (13–72) is dedicated to Aristotle, the second (73–205) to Nietzsche. The two parts have few points of connection, except where Valentini uses Nietzsche's several references to Aristotle to make a comparison with the principal points that emerged from his discussion of Nietzsche. Thus, when mentioned in the second part of the volume, Aristotle receives a retrospectively “Nietzschean” interpretation, which criticizes the logocentrism of his aesthetic theory. Even Valentini's interpretation of Nietzsche's philosophy is accompanied by reflections that go beyond Nietzsche himself, to Heidegger and Wittgenstein. And Valentini is interested only in the concept of representation in The Birth of Tragedy and other works of that period, such that his theorization of the concept is based only on Schopenhauer's account in The World as Will and Representation.For his interpretation of Aristotle in the first part Valentini does not limit himself to an analysis of the Poetics (the traditional focus of studies on the theory of tragedy), but instead tries to inscribe his interpretation in a broader discussion of Aristotle's entire metaphysics. The famous distinction between poetry and history, made in chapter 9 of the Poetics, makes poetry, and thus also tragedy as one of its forms, a representation of the universal, and therefore more philosophical than history, which concerns only contingent facts. Furthermore, poetry is no more than a part, or a form, of theorein (contemplation); it represents things not as they are, but rather as they should be—that is, it represents them in that form that does not belong to them completely as natural beings, but rather belongs to them as metaphysical entities, as ideas. This “ideal form” is that which can be recognized by the spectator of tragedy, and which can be appropriated through a cognitive act. Valentini concludes that, in some way, poetic mimesis represents that which cannot be represented, and makes knowable what is otherwise unknowable.If for Aristotle poetic mimesis aims to represent things as they should be once the final form of entelechy is reached, Nietzsche, in contrast, concentrates on the representation of the dynamis, that never manifest process that precedes the act. For Valentini, the figure of Dionysus allows Nietzsche to represent the essence of reality itself, which excludes the act and the ideal, and maintains only the inexhaustible potentiality of dynamis or dynamic tension.The fourth and last chapter introduces another contender in the contest between Aristotle and Nietzsche, Heidegger. Here Valentini proposes an audacious reading of (Schopenhauer's and) Nietzsche's notion of representation on the basis of Heidegger's concept of truth as aletheia. Instead of reading Schopenhauer's opposition between world and representation as insuperable, Nietzsche sees in tragic thought the acceptance of the identity of real world and appearance. In this sense, Valentini finds a resemblance between Nietzsche's and Heidegger's conceptions of truth and the true world. Thus Nietzsche's concept of tragic truth is not simply a form of “disclosure” of the veil of Maya. It is rather a real form of what Heidegger calls Un-verborgenheit, or a-letheia—the present and manifest appearance of the not-hidden. Valentini tries then to interpret some ancient figures related to tragedy and considered by Nietzsche, such as Socrates and Oedipus, as representative of logical thought's resistance to the mystery of the aletheia, of how logical thought searches for reasons where all is revealed without reasons. On Valentini's reading, from Euripides onward, Greek tragedy tried to make explicit, or disclose, what until then, rather than simply hidden, was implicitly manifest. Putting aside the philological accuracy of this interpretation, this parallel between Nietzsche's conception of tragedy and Heidegger's concept of truth as aletheia is an interesting interpretative suggestion, which might be fruitfully used to explain the value of the tragic experience in Nietzsche's work. Another interesting parallel, which unfortunately is not developed sufficiently in the book, is that between Nietzsche's idea of knowledge as a form of intuition and the Wittgensteinian concept of übersichtliche Darstellung. Little thorough work has been done on the relationship between Nietzsche and Wittgenstein, even if this lack has been observed by many and research is starting to move in this direction.In conclusion, Valentini's book is an interesting philosophical work. Indeed, it should be read in one go, because it is characterized by a strong argumentative framework. However, the connection between the two parts of the book is perhaps too loose, and it is clearly biased toward the Nietzsche part, the discussion of Aristotle being used primarily as a reference point for the treatment of Nietzsche. Unfortunately, the complexity of the style and the difficulty posed by the sometimes extremely technical language also make the book impracticable for anyone without a thorough knowledge of Italian and the Aristotelian and Heideggerian philosophical lexicon in Italian. The almost complete absence of long quotations and of commentary on them gives the impression of “thinking without breaks,” while the frequent use of very brief quotations in the text breaks the flow of reading. This makes the work decidedly difficult to read and runs the risk of the words losing their status as “the author's,” and becoming merely “the commentator's.” Thus Valentini does not leave space to follow the traces of his argumentation, but rather involves the reader in a very complex and laborious stylistic-philosophical exercise. Still, while certainly not a “philological” work of history of philosophy, Valentini's book can be profitably read as a philosophical essay that gives interesting and often novel clues for reflecting on Nietzsche, Aristotle, and Heidegger.

Referência(s)
Altmetric
PlumX